Go back
Evidence, Induction and Drinking Games

Evidence, Induction and Drinking Games

Debates

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
Only if it's quick and easy. Otherwise I'll take your word - I just don't see it.

My point is, can your objection be addressed by something analagous to the fix applied to set theory to eliminate its classic paradox? Can the rational agent be defined as being restricted to analyzing things in a universe in which he does not exist, thereby eliminating your objection?
Perhaps, but I'd bet there are propositions relating to rational beings in other universes that would lead to counterexamples.

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
10 edits
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr


Since P is a logical truth, H is logically equivalent to the conjunction
P & H.

Since rational beings would have the same credence in logically equivalent hypotheses, he would have great credence in P & H.

The rational agent only has great credence in P & H if he acknowledges that P is a logical truth. If he has no evidence regarding the truth of P, which is likely by H which you assert, he would have to have less credence in P&H than in H by virtue of his rationality.

Rational beings place the same credence in logically equivalent hypotheses, but P&H is only logically equivalent to H once the truth value of P is known to the rational being. This is because P&H is not formally equivalent to H; it depends on the actual truth value of P. (You didn't mean that P is a formal tautology, did you?) For example, you can't tell me, for some Z that I formulate, whether Z&H is logically equivalent to H until you know that Z is true, so a being in another universe who knows that Z is true can't simply conclude that you will accept Z&H as logically equivalent to H. For all the rational being knows, P could be false, so you can't require him to accept the logical equivalence and put great credence in P&H.

EDIT: OK, I'm done editing. Feel free to respond without fear of more.

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
The rational agent only has great credence in P & H if he acknowledges that P is a logical truth. If he has no evidence regarding the truth of P, which is likely by H which you assert, he would have to have less credence in P&H than in H by virtue of his rationality.

Rational beings place the same credence in logically equivalent hypotheses, but ...[text shortened]... redence in P&H.

EDIT: OK, I'm done editing. Feel free to respond without fear of more.
If S is rational, the S knows that P is a logical truth, and thus places great credence in P. Are you assuming that RC is using the term 'rational' to refer to less than perfect theoretical rationality? Since P is a logical truth (a theorem of logic), it is logically equivalent to the conjunction of P & H, because P and P&H yield equivalent truth tables.

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
10 edits
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr
If S is rational, the S knows that P is a logical truth, and thus places great credence in P.
OK, you are saying that P is a tautology. Then my objection to your proof is different.

P is defined: Let P be some logical truth such that, in this world, it is very probable on our evidence that nobody has great credence in P.

If S exists, then P cannot exist, for if S exists, then it is certain on our evidence that somebody - namely S - has great credence in every logical truth.

So I don't see how your proof even gets started since P can't exist.

Or if you're going to stipulate that P exists, then it follows that S can't exist and your proof concludes nothing. That is, there is no entity holding the absurd state of beliefs.

[End of Edits]

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
1 edit
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
P is defined: Let P be some logical truth such that, in this world, it is very probable on our evidence that nobody has great credence in P.

If S exists, then P cannot exist, for if S exists, then it is certain, due to his rationality, that somebody - namely S - has great credenece in every rational truth.

So I don't see how your proof even ge r proof concludes nothing. That is, there is no entity holding the absurd state of beliefs.
The proof is a reductio. It shows that there are some propositions such that a contradiction arises when we apply the epistemic probability criterion to it. So, not all propositions are such that their epistemic probability is determined by the credence a rational agent would lend to them. The fact that the proof results in a contradiction is the very point!

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
1 edit
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr
The proof is a reductio. It shows that there are some propositions such that a contradiction arises when we apply the epistemic probability criterion to it. So, not all propositions are such that their epistemic probability is determined by the credence a rational agent would lend to them.
Hmmmmm. I'll have to think it over. I didn't even realize it was a reductio. I'm not clear on what supposition you are claiming leads to a contradiction, and which you thus reject and in turn conclude its negation. I don't see it as part of your proof.

At any rate, I have to go out of town for four days. I hope to rejoin this discussion when I return.

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
4 edits
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr
The fact that the proof results in a contradiction is the very point!
But I don't think it does yield a contradiction, since you haven't demonstrated or stipulated that both P and S exist.

If you stipulate that they both exist, then that is the supposition that yields a contradiction, and which you must reject. But I can do that rejection a priori without appealing to the proof but merely by pointing to their definitions.

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
1 edit
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
Hmmmmm. I'll have to think it over. I didn't even realize it was a reductio. I'm not clear on what supposition you are claiming leads to a contradiction, and which you thus reject and in turn conclude its negation. I don't see it as part of your proof.

At any rate, I have to go out of town for four days. I hope to rejoin this discussion when I return.
Well, it is certainly possible that there are logical theorems complex or opaque enough that no actual agent would lend a high degree of credence to them, even though their objective probability is (of course) 1. So I don't think it would be wise to adopt a theory of epistemic probability that entails that these sorts of theorems can't exist. It's probably prudent to reject the epistemic probability criterion...

Have fun on your trip, Herr Doctor. I'll talk to you when you return.

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
1 edit
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
But I don't think it does yield a contradiction, since you haven't demonstrated that both P and S exist.
You don't need to demonstrate the truth of premises to engage in a reductio. Reductios show that if a premise is true, and if we assume something further, then a contradiction results. In virtue of deriving a contradiction, we are warranted by the rules of the propositional calculus, to infer the negation of any premise upon which the contradiction is based. In this case, which premise ouught we reject? Should we reject that it is possible that a theorem of the sort described exists? Obviously not, because it obviously is possible for there to be a logical truth that no actual person lends any credence to. So, we should reject the other assumption that led to the contradiction, and that was the application of the epistemic probability criterion to the hypothesized theorem.

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
1 edit
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr
Obviously not, because it obviously is possible for there to be a logical truth that no actual person lends any credence to.
If you're going to distinguish between real rational agents and theoretical rational agents, then I would suggest that your conclusion contains an equivocation and is not an absurdity at all.

"But this entails that he has great credence in the proposition 'P, and nobody has great credence that P', which is absurd."

Under your distinction, this really reads:

"But this entails that the theoretically rational agent has great credence in the proposition 'P, and no actual agent has great credence that P', which is absurd."

But the latter is actually not absurd.

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr


Have fun on your trip, Herr Doctor. I'll talk to you when you return.
If I don't go home to Jesus. I'm going skiing, so there is a non-zero probability that I will perish and our next conversation will be in the big Spirituality forum in the sky.

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
If you're going to distinguish between real rational agents and theoretical rational agents, then I would suggest that your conclusion contains an equivocation and is not an absurdity at all.

"But this entails that he has great credence in the proposition 'P, and nobody has great credence that P', which is absurd."

Under your distinction, this ...[text shortened]... has great credence that P', which is absurd."

But the latter is actually not absurd.
There's no equivoation in the proof. It is the theorist, that by invoking the e.p.criterion, invites the rational agent into the domain of discourse by way of an existentially quantified supposition (i.e., (Ex)(X is perfectly rational and has our evidence)) and then conditionalizes upon that supposition. But the antecedent of the conditional has contradictory entailments when the proposition evaluated is something like P.

DoctorScribbles
BWA Soldier

Tha Brotha Hood

Joined
13 Dec 04
Moves
49088
Clock
23 Feb 06
4 edits
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by bbarr
There's no equivoation in the proof.
Does the 'nobody' in P refer to actual or theoretically rational agents?

If the former, then the alleged absurdity is not actually an absurdity for the reason I just cited.

If the latter, then "But the antecedent of the conditional has contradictory entailments when the proposition evaluated is something like P" is immaterial since propositions like P cannot exist (since no theoretical rational agents can fail to have credence in a logical truth, by definition).

If it refers to all agents, theoretical and actual, then the same objection as for the latter case holds.

bbarr
Chief Justice

Center of Contention

Joined
14 Jun 02
Moves
17381
Clock
23 Feb 06
3 edits
Vote Up
Vote Down

Originally posted by DoctorScribbles
Does the 'nobody' in P refer to actual or theoretically rational agents?

If the former, then the alleged absurdity is not actually an absurdity for the reason I just cited.

If the latter, then "But the antecedent of the conditional has contradictory entailments when the proposition evaluated is something like P" is immaterial since propositions ...[text shortened]... to all agents, theoretical and actual, then the same objection as for the latter case holds.
The 'nobody' in P refers to actual agents. When the e.p.criterion is applied, another agent is brought into the domain of agents via an hypthetical assumption on the part of the theorist ("Suppose there is some rational agent that has our evidence, if so...." ). This agent is such that when we suppose that he has our evidence, a contradiction results.

If the latter, then "But the antecedent of the conditional has contradictory entailments when the proposition evaluated is something like P" is immaterial since propositions like P cannot exist...

The fact that propositions like P cannot exist if we suppose that S exists is the very point the reductio establishes!

X
Cancerous Bus Crash

p^2.sin(phi)

Joined
06 Sep 04
Moves
25076
Clock
23 Feb 06
1 edit
Vote Up
Vote Down

Bayesian Masturbation going on in this thread!

Cookies help us deliver our Services. By using our Services or clicking I agree, you agree to our use of cookies. Learn More.